Introduction

Game theory helps frame the strategic interactions among countries (Schelling, 1960), with global climate negotiations as a prominent example (Barrett, 2007, 2003, 1994; MacKay et al., 2015). That holds for multilateral negotiations under the umbrella of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change as well as for bilateral negotiations and those among smaller groups of countries. Science points to the need for ambitious climate action (IPCC, 2018). Many countries are indeed pursuing ambitious action on their own (Aklin and Mildenberger, 2018), only in part for strategic reasons (Kotchen, 2018; Nordhaus, 2020, 2015).Footnote 1 Meanwhile, assuming symmetric players in a weakest-link game (Sandler, 1997, chap. 2), as long as one country, or group of countries, prefers high mitigation to low (H  L), while the other prefers L  H, an ambitious negotiated agreement (H) is unlikely. We here introduce what we consider to be the simplest possible game-theoretic framework that demonstrates this lack of an ambitious negotiated climate agreement. Doing so allows us to communicate and synthesize results of previously published research on climate negotiations and geoengineering (G) (e.g., Millard-Ball, 2012; Moreno-Cruz, 2015; Sandler, 2018; Urpelainen, 2012).

Simple game theory explains lack of ambitious climate agreement

Consider two countries or groups of countries, 1 and 2. Both countries would have to prefer H to L for H to prevail (Table 1) (Nash, 1951). This holds as long as the aggregate level of mitigation is characterized by the minimum of each country’s mitigation policy, a stylized representation of the arithmetic of climate negotiations focused on strategic interaction among symmetric players (MacKay et al., 2015).

Table 1 Climate policy resulting from each pair of moves. High mitigation agreement (H) is only possible if both players choose H over low (L) mitigation.

This weakest-link negotiation game might be the simplest representation of the lack of collective action. It stands in contrast to models of total mitigation as the sum of each country’s contribution (Barrett, 2007; Sandler, 2018), though aggregating mitigation efforts, too, can lead to a weakest-link game under some reasonable conditions. If the combination of diverging mitigation efforts ((L1, H2) or (H1, L2)) led to moderate overall mitigation effort M, it might be reasonable to treat M and L the same for purposes of this analysis. That might hold especially if there is a threshold of sorts between M and H. If so, only the outcome H might lead to stabilizing global climates, while both L and M would imply indefinite warming, albeit at different speeds.

Our framework also assumes that mitigation is costly, with H costlier than L. Mitigation might not be as costly as often assumed (Gillingham and Stock, 2018), leading, for example, to some countries pursuing ambitious climate action on their own (Wagner et al., 2015), or it might be in some countries’ self-interest to pursue more ambitious mitigation policies to coax others into doing the same (Kotchen, 2018; Nordhaus, 2020, 2015). Nordhaus (2020, 2015), in particular, points to how powerful countries taking ambitious climate mitigation action could force others into following suit. Either possibility may indeed help break through the global climate negotiations logjam (Barrett, 2007). Failing that, Table 1 presents the simplest possible explanation for the woeful lack of ambitious climate action to date. Any player would only play H, if H is also the preferred outcome of the other player(s). Otherwise the one player choosing H would incur the extra mitigation cost in vain. This is often described as the “free-rider” problem, the direct result of climate mitigation’s public goods nature (Baumol, 1952).

Geoengineering is cheap and imperfect, and all-too tempting

Geoengineering (G) introduces an entirely new set of challenges into global climate policy negotiations. Some have focused on G crowding out ambitious mitigation, necessitating complex governance regimes (Quaas et al., 2017; Weitzman, 2015). This often comes under the heading of “moral hazard” (Keith, 2000; Lin, 2013; Wagner and Zizzamia, 2020). The mere availability of G might also do the opposite, encouraging more mitigation action (Merk et al., 2016). In strategic climate negotiations, the threat of risky G by players suffering most from L has indeed been shown to have the potential to lead to H (Millard-Ball, 2012; Moreno-Cruz, 2015; Urpelainen, 2012).

In contrast to mitigation, geoengineering (G) is often characterized as fast, cheap, and imperfect (Keith, 2000; Mahajan et al., 2018). Here we drop “fast” and focus on the latter two. In fact, while G is often synonymous with solar radiation management or modification (SRM), with carbon dioxide removal (CDR) instead best thought as expensive mitigation (Moreno-Cruz et al., 2018), here some CDR techniques could count, too. For example, ocean fertilization in an attempt to remove carbon from the atmosphere might be “slow” yet is also both cheap and imperfect. The combination makes it risky, widening the list of possible G techniques relevant to this analysis.

Modelling G necessitates extending our game to two periods: first, players choose mitigation levels H or L; second, they decide on G. The latter could be a decision on degree: how much G to pursue. For simplicity, we assume it is a zero-one decision: whether to pursue G or not. Indeed, G is so cheap (Smith and Wagner, 2018) that the largest hurdle is the willingness to engage in it in the first place.Footnote 2 G is also so powerful that one country’s choice determines the overall outcome. While for mitigation, the ambition of the global agreement here equals the minimum level of ambition across the two players, for G it only takes one player to pursue it for the entire world to experience the outcome—both its potential (net) benefits, and the potentially large risks. Moreover, we assume that the aggregate level of mitigation is irrelevant to a geoengineered climate, so that the climate resulting from the players’ moves across both periods can be characterized by H, L, or G. Conversely, the preferences of each player can be reduced to their rankings over possible resulting climates H, L, or G.

Table 2 summarizes the impact of G on the negotiated outcome: As in Table 1, H only happens if both players prefer it. Meanwhile, either player resorting to G implies the entire world facing its consequences. These properties not least explain G’s “free-driver” effect (Barrett, 2008; Schelling, 1996; Victor et al., 2009; Wagner and Weitzman, 2012; Weitzman, 2015). G is at once so cheap and powerful that a single player’s preferences dominate the outcome, regardless of how many other players there are.

Table 2 Climate policy resulting from each pair of moves. Low mitigation (L) without geoengineering (G) dominates high mitigation (H) (Table 1), while G dominates all.

Simple game theory of how availability of G can induce H

If all players agreed on either of the three possible negotiation positions as their top choice, the outcome would be just that, shown in bold italics in Table 3. If any player preferred G to all other choices, G would win (shown in italics). That leaves four cases.

Table 3 Climatic policy outcomes depending on each player’s full set of preferences. Availability of geoengineering (G) could lead to high mitigation agreement (H, in bold roman). Symmetric outcomes are omitted for simplicity.

In all four, one player ranks L as the top choice, while the other prefers H above all else. That situation mimics the “simple” negotiation, shown in Table 1, save for the addition of G. If G were ranked last by both, the game would collapse to the simple negotiation, where one ranks L  H and the other ranks H  L. G does not interfere. L wins. Conversely, if G were to be ranked second by both players, G would win. Two cases remain.

If the player who prefers L ranked G  H while the other player who prefers H ranked L  G, L would win. G does not alter the outcome, as both players prefer L to G. That, however, would imply that those most hurt by climate change, and thus most interested in pursuing H, would rank L  G. That might be a justifiable ranking, given G’s inherent risks. But desperation can beget risky choices.

Here this willingness on the part of those preferring H  L to engage in risky choices to avoid the worst implies that those same players might also rank G  L. G is not the first choice, but it might be better than L: H  G  L. The fundamental assumption here—and this is indeed an assumption—is that, among those most vulnerable to a low mitigation climate, expensive and safe H is still preferred to cheap yet risky G. (If that were not the case, and G  H, G would win.) Conversely, those ranking L  H reveal themselves to be relatively less affected by climate damages and, thus, less inclined to agree to an ambitious mitigation agreement. At the same time, the perceived possibility of a disastrous impact of G implies that they might be less willing to engage in risky geoengineering, resulting in L  H  G.

These rankings, in turn, immediately lead to the final case, with H (in bold in Table 3) as the outcome, induced by the availability of G. It is also the only situation with H as the outcome despite only one player, or group of players, ranking H first. The threat of G leads both players to rank H  G, although one player would still prefer L  H.

Discussion

We are far from the first to analyse the impact of the mere availability of G on mitigation outcomes (e.g., Keith, 2000; Merk et al., 2016; Quaas et al., 2017; Sandler, 2018; Wagner and Zizzamia, 2020; Weitzman, 2015). Others have indeed argued how the threat of G, coupled with G’s inherent uncertainties, can lead to more ambitious mitigation action within and across countries (Heyen, 2015; Millard-Ball, 2012; Moreno-Cruz, 2015; Urpelainen, 2012; Victor et al., 2009).Footnote 3 Here we boil this reasoning down to its bare essentials, focusing on simple, relative preference ordering of each player over climate outcomes H, L, and G. These players could be singular actors in bilateral negotiations. They could also stand in for groups of players. G’s fundamental characteristics might lead players previously stuck in a low-mitigation equilibrium L to consider H.

For G to induce H, the threat of deploying G must be credible. And it must indeed be a threat—something opting for H can avoid. All that relies on G being risky and shrouded in uncertainty. The more research discovers about G, decreasing its potential risks and uncertainties for everyone, the less it might be able to induce H. Indeed, a new discovery might affect the players’ expected payoffs, making G the worst policy outcome in case of bad news, or the preferred one in case of good news. Conversely, the possibility of G deployed as a supplement to H might have similar effects of helping to induce H, but it may well be too tempting to trade off some mitigation action for moderate geoengineering (Moreno-Cruz et al., 2018).

Lastly, if any player—a singular state, for example, tempted by G to maintain the high-emitting status quo—were to prefer G altogether, the free-driver effect kicks in and G prevails. The only possible solution in such a scenario to prevent the free driver from forcing G upon everyone else: strong governance at the global level, effectively leading to a ban on unilateral G.

The mere availability of G, of course, is no guarantee of inducing H. Viewed in the right light, and with the bare minimum of oft-invoked assumptions, it might help break the decades-long logjam of climate negotiations—both formally at the international level, and informally among smaller groups of state and possibly non-state actors (Reynolds and Wagner, 2019).

Methods

The solution relies on a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium among players in a non-cooperative game (Nash, 1951; Selten, 1965).